友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

on sophistical refutations-第14章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!





adopted in refutations on side issues。







                                28







  Also; those refutations that bring one to their conclusion through



the consequent you should show up in the course of the argument



itself。 The mode in which consequences follow is twofold。 For the



argument either is that as the universal follows on its



particular…as (e。g。) 'animal' follows from 'man'…so does the



particular on its universal: for the claim is made that if A is always



found with B; then B also is always found with A。 Or else it



proceeds by way of the opposites of the terms involved: for if A



follows B; it is claimed that A's opposite will follow B's opposite。



On this latter claim the argument of Melissus also depends: for he



claims that because that which has come to be has a beginning; that



which has not come to be has none; so that if the heaven has not



come to be; it is also eternal。 But that is not so; for the sequence



is vice versa。







                                29







  In the case of any refutations whose reasoning depends on some



addition; look and see if upon its subtraction the absurdity follows



none the less: and then if so; the answerer should point this out; and



say that he granted the addition not because he really thought it; but



for the sake of the argument; whereas the questioner has not used it



for the purpose of his argument at all。







                                30







  To meet those refutations which make several questions into one; one



should draw a distinction between them straight away at the start。 For



a question must be single to which there is a single answer; so that



one must not affirm or deny several things of one thing; nor one thing



of many; but one of one。 But just as in the case of ambiguous terms;



an attribute belongs to a term sometimes in both its senses; and



sometimes in neither; so that a simple answer does one; as it happens;



no harm despite the fact that the question is not simple; so it is



in these cases of double questions too。 Whenever; then; the several



attributes belong to the one subject; or the one to the many; the



man who gives a simple answer encounters no obstacle even though he



has committed this mistake: but whenever an attribute belongs to one



subject but not to the other; or there is a question of a number of



attributes belonging to a number of subjects and in one sense both



belong to both; while in another sense; again; they do not; then there



is trouble; so that one must beware of this。 Thus (e。g。) in the



following arguments: Supposing to be good and B evil; you will; if you



give a single answer about both; be compelled to say that it is true



to call these good; and that it is true to call them evil and likewise



to call them neither good nor evil (for each of them has not each



character); so that the same thing will be both good and evil and



neither good nor evil。 Also; since everything is the same as itself



and different from anything else; inasmuch as the man who answers



double questions simply can be made to say that several things are



'the same' not as other things but 'as themselves'; and also that they



are different from themselves; it follows that the same things must be



both the same as and different from themselves。 Moreover; if what is



good becomes evil while what is evil is good; then they must both



become two。 So of two unequal things each being equal to itself; it



will follow that they are both equal and unequal to themselves。



  Now these refutations fall into the province of other solutions as



well: for 'both' and 'all' have more than one meaning; so that the



resulting affirmation and denial of the same thing does not occur;



except verbally: and this is not what we meant by a refutation。 But it



is clear that if there be not put a single question on a number of



points; but the answerer has affirmed or denied one attribute only



of one subject only; the absurdity will not come to pass。







                                31







  With regard to those who draw one into repeating the same thing a



number of times; it is clear that one must not grant that predications



of relative terms have any meaning in abstraction by themselves;



e。g。 that 'double' is a significant term apart from the whole phrase



'double of half' merely on the ground that it figures in it。 For ten



figures in 'ten minus one' and in 'not do'; and generally the



affirmation in the negation; but for all that; suppose any one were to



say; 'This is not white'; he does not say that it is white。 The bare



word 'double'; one may perhaps say; has not even any meaning at all;



any more than has 'the' in 'the half': and even if it has a meaning;



yet it has not the same meaning as in the combination。 Nor is



'knowledge' the same thing in a specific branch of it (suppose it;



e。g。 to be 'medical knowledge') as it is in general: for in general it



was the 'knowledge of the knowable'。 In the case of terms that are



predicated of the terms through which they are defined; you should say



the same thing; that the term defined is not the same in abstraction



as it is in the whole phrase。 For 'concave' has a general meaning



which is the same in the case of a snub nose; and of a bandy leg;



but when added to either substantive nothing prevents it from



differentiating its meaning; in fact it bears one sense as applied



to the nose; and another as applied to the leg: for in the former



connexion it means 'snub' and in the latter 'bandyshaped'; i。e。 it



makes no difference whether you say 'a snub nose' or 'a concave nose'。



Moreover; the expression must not be granted in the nominative case:



for it is a falsehood。 For snubness is not a concave nose but



something (e。g。 an affection) belonging to a nose: hence; there is



no absurdity in supposing that the snub nose is a nose possessing



the concavity that belongs to a nose。







                                32







  With regard to solecisms; we have previously said what it is that



appears to bring them about; the method of their solution will be



clear in the course of the arguments themselves。 Solecism is the



result aimed at in all arguments of the following kind: 'Is a thing



truly that which you truly call it?' 'Yes'。 'But; speaking of a stone;



you call him real: therefore of a stone it follows that 〃him is



real〃。' No: rather; talking of a stone means not saying which' but



'whom'; and not 'that' but 'him'。 If; then; any one were to ask; 'Is a



stone him whom you truly call him?' he would be generally thought



not to be speaking good Greek; any more than if he were to ask; 'Is he



what you call her?' Speak in this way of a 'stick' or any neuter word;



and the difference does not break out。 For this reason; also; no



solecism is incurred; suppose any one asks; 'Is a thing what you say



it to be?' 'Yes'。 'But; speaking of a stick; you call it real:



therefore; of a stick it follows that it is real。' 'Stone'; however;



and 'he' have masculine designations。 Now suppose some one were to



ask; 'Can 〃he〃 be a she〃 (a female)?'; and then again; 'Well; but is



not he Coriscus?' and then were to say; 'Then he is a 〃she〃;' he has



not proved the solecism; even if the name 'Coriscus' does signify a



'she'; if; on the other hand; the answerer does not grant this: this



point must be put as an additional question: while if neither is it



the fact nor does he grant it; then the sophist has not proved his



case either in fact or as against the person he has been



questioning。 In like manner; then; in the above instance as well it



must be definitely put that 'he' means the stone。 If; however; this



neither is so nor is granted; the conclusion must not be stated:



though it follows apparently; because the case (the accusative);



that is really unlike; appears to be like the nominative。 'Is it



true to say that this object is what you call it by name?' 'Yes'。 'But



you call it by the name of a shield: this object therefore is 〃of a



shield〃。' No: not necessarily; because the meaning of 'this object' is



not 'of a shield' but 'a shield': 'of a shield' would be the meaning



of 'this object's'。 Nor again if 'He is what you call him by name';



while 'the name you call him by is Cleon's'; is he therefore



'Cleon's': for he is not 'Cleon's'; for what was said was that 'He;



not his; is what I call him by name'。 For the question; if put in



the latter way; would not even be Greek。 'Do you know this?' 'Yes。'



'But this is he: therefore you know he'。 No: rather 'this' has not the



same meaning in 'Do you know this?' as in 'This is a stone'; in the



first it stands for an accusative; in the second for a nominative



case。 'When you have understanding of anything; do you understand it?
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!